In constructing an ethical theory, one consideration is: who
has ethical standing? That is, whose
interests “count” when considering “right” behavior? Utilitarians like Bentham (and today, philosopher
Peter Singer) feel that all sentient animals—all creatures capable of feeling
pain—are due equal respect and
consideration. No preference should be shown
to humans or to Americans or to people of my particular family line.
Adam Smith would not go along with that. He argued that we owe greater duty and
respect towards those closest to us: our
duty to our own mother, for example, is greater than our duty to an unknown elderly
women on another continent. Moral
preference is necessary in some
situations.
The issue of boundaries of ethical obligation is quite
important, particularly when we consider global warming, whose greatest impacts
will be in 100 years when few currently alive will be around. Issues of intergenerational justice are a
huge problem. Should we consider those
who live in two generations receive equal moral consideration to those living
now? To economists, discounting future
generations’ interests makes logical sense, but may put us on difficult ethical
footing.
This brings us to a fascinating book by Richard Moss. The
Mandala of Being is about how humans construct identities that create
walls between people and different groups of people. But it is more than an analysis, it also has
a prescription for gently disengaging one’s feelings, beliefs, and thoughts
from the notion of identity, and by doing so, getting us closer to the experience
of who we are in essence. This essence, he claims, allows us to be on an equal footing
with others on the planet.
In Moss’ view, we form “identities” as a survival
mechanism. Thoughts, feelings, and
actions arise in particular contexts in which a child encounters stress. Our identities grow out of how we react to perceived
threats. Identity is essential for
survival and motivation, and cultural ideology and mythology are key parts of that
identity.
But identity is also what keeps us apart from others who are
different. Hence, tolerance only comes
when we are able to step outside identity and the thoughts, feelings and
actions associated with it.
Moss explores a psychological mechanism that will be
familiar to practitioners of Eastern philosophy—the practice of living in the “now”
of awareness. Awareness happens when we are able to gently let go of thoughts of
past and future, of ego and of others, and simply “be.” Moss notes that he believes this is the essence
of a human being. There are a multitude of techniques for
getting in this state of original awareness, such as by focused breathing, meditation,
repetitive physical activity (“runner’s high”) or playing games.
From this state of awareness one has a very different
conception, Moss claims, of our relationships with others. From this place of blissful awareness we are
far more likely to be tolerant of those who are different—because we can see that
differences arise out of identity creation and not inherent or intrinsic disparities.
By contrast, Moss argues that moral absolutist are trapped in
an identity that limits their experience of the now awareness. That explanation may be insulting to moral
absolutists, but Moss has a much gentler way of getting to this point than I
have.
At a future point I will describe the Mandala—essentially a
psychological visual chart that relates past to present and subject (ourselves)
to objects (others). Whether you agree
or disagree with Moss, his work is interesting to economists because he is
directly addressing the meaning of happiness that has been the object of much
attention recently.